Slouching Towards Gomorrah (30 page)

Read Slouching Towards Gomorrah Online

Authors: Robert H. Bork

BOOK: Slouching Towards Gomorrah
5.58Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub

“Some 77 percent of women with incomes under 100 percent or between 100 and 149 percent of the poverty level [in 1987, the federally designated poverty level for a nonfarm family of four was $11,200] said they were having an abortion because they could not afford to have a child, compared with 69 percent of those with incomes between 150 and 199 percent and 60 percent of those with incomes at or above 200 percent of the poverty level.“
10
The can’t-afford category thus included a great many women who, by most reckonings, could afford to have a baby and certainly could have put the baby up for adoption.

This demonstration that abortion is almost always a birth control technique rather than a response to a serious problem with the mothers or the fetus’s health must have been a considerable embarrassment to the pro-abortion forces. Perhaps for that reason no survey by them seems to have been reported since. More recent statistics by anti-abortion groups, however, bear out the conclusions to be drawn from the Guttmacher Institute study. The
reasons most women give for having an abortion are “social”: a baby would affect their educations, jobs, lives, or they felt unable to handle it economically, their partners did not want babies, etc.
11

Perhaps the most instructive episode demonstrating the brutalization of our culture by abortion was the fight over “partial birth abortions.” These abortions are performed late in the pregnancy. The baby is delivered feet first until only the head remains within the mother. The aborting physician inserts scissors into the back of the infant’s skull and opens the blades to produce a hole. The child’s brains are then vacuumed out, the skull collapses, and the rest of the newly-made corpse is removed. If the head had been allowed to come out of the mother, killing the baby then would be the criminal act of infanticide.

When it was proposed to outlaw this hideous procedure, which obviously causes extreme pain to the baby, the pro-abortion forces in Congress and elsewhere made false statements to fend off the legislation or to justify an anticipated presidential veto. Planned Parenthood and the National Abortion and Reproductive Rights Action League stated that the general anaesthesia given the mother killed the fetus so that there is no such thing as a partial birth abortion. Physicians promptly rebutted the claim. Local anaesthesia, which is most often used in these abortions, has no effect on the baby, and general anaesthesia not only does not kill the baby, it provides little or no pain-killing effect to the baby. The vice president of the Society for Obstetric Anesthesia and Perinatology said that the claim was “crazy” and that “Anesthesia does not kill an infant if you don’t kill the mother.“
12
Two doctors who perform partial birth abortions stated that the majority of fetuses aborted in this fashion are alive until the end of the procedure.
13

Other opponents of a ban on partial birth abortions claimed that it was used only when necessary to protect the mother’s life. Unfortunately for that argument, the physician who is the best-known practitioner of these abortions stated in 1993 that 80 percent of them are “purely elective,” not necessary to save the mother’s life or health.
14
Partial birth understates the matter. The baby is outside the mother except for its head, which is kept in the mother only to avoid a charge of infanticide. Full birth is inches away and could easily be accomplished.

President Clinton did, in fact, veto the bill banning partial birth abortions, demanding a vague exception for health that would have amounted to a ratification of almost all such abortions. His veto and the feminist demand for what is, in truth, infanticide underscore the casual brutality born of nihilism that is an ever more prominent feature of our culture.

No amount of discussion, no citation of evidence, can alter the opinions of radical feminists about abortion. One evening I naively remarked in a talk that those who favor the right to abort would likely change their minds if they could be convinced that a human being was being killed. I was startled at the anger that statement provoked in several women present. One of them informed me in no uncertain terms that the issue had nothing to do with the humanity of the fetus but was entirely about the woman’s freedom. It is here that radical egalitarianism reinforces radical individualism in supporting the abortion right. Justice Harry Blackmun, who wrote
Roe
and who never offered the slightest constitutional defense of it, simply remarked that the decision was a landmark on women’s march to equality. Equality, in this view, means that if men do not bear children, women should not have to either. Abortion is seen as a way for women to escape the idea that biology is destiny, and from the tyranny of the family role.

The attitude towards human life that abortion fosters affects the debate about other matters as well. Tissue from fetuses is used for medical research and in treating certain disorders, such as Parkinson’s disease. The difficulty is that fetal tissue is far more valuable if the fetus is alive when the tissue is removed. Partial birth abortions, for example, produce brain tissue from a living child. The next step has been proposed. Science can create human life outside the mother’s body. A panel appointed by the National Institutes of Health recommended that human embryos be created in the laboratory so that they may be subjected to experiments that will kill them. One’s first thought might be that the panel consisted of technocrats oblivious to moral considerations, but that is not at all the case. Their report and the sources upon which it relies offer a philosophy to justify what they recommend. The embryos they would create may be human but, the panel said, are not entitled to a “personhood” that requires respect. Personhood is determined by our decision to bestow it. That decision determines
whether or not the life involved is protectable. According to the report, an embryo that does not have “potential for further development” is not protectable, and the embryos they would create lack such potential.

The argument is breathtaking for, as Father Richard John Neuhaus observes: “Here the reasoning is utterly circular: An embryo is not protectable because it has no potential for further development, and it has no potential for further development because, having determined that it is not protectable, researchers will not permit it to develop further.“
15
The separation of humanity from personhood in this fashion is, as already mentioned, an argument used by pro-abortionists: personhood is conferred when the fetus can live outside the womb or if the mother values the life she carries, etc. The philosophical separation of humanity and personhood carries ominous overtones for the very ill, the very old, the senile, and perhaps for others.

A similar progression may be underway with respect to organ transplants. The “dead donor” rule protects those who have agreed to give their organs for transplantation after death from the possibility of being killed by the removal of their organs while they are still alive. An exception to the rule is now proposed, however. The exception would apply only to anencephalics, children born without the thinking part of the brain. These unfortunates will usually live only a few days and when they die their organs are useless as transplants. The American Medical Association’s Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs recommends the removal of anencephalics’ organs before they die. The members seek a change in the current law, which forbids removal of organs from living persons. The Council’s report assures us: “Because anencephalic neonates lack functioning cerebral hemispheres, they never experience any degree of consciousness. They never have thoughts, feelings, sensations, desires or emotions.“
16
The Council takes this position even though it concedes that these babies “may be able to breathe, suck, engage in spontaneous movements of their eyes, arms, and legs, respond to noxious stimuli with crying or avoidance maneuvers, and exhibit facial expressions typical of healthy infants.“
17
Charles Krauthammer reports that they can also exhibit complex behaviors such as consolability, conditioning, and irritability, and some even distinguish their mothers from other people. It is, he says,
simply unknown and unknowable whether anencephalics possess consciousness.
18

It is proposed, nonetheless, that anencephalics’ organs be taken while they are alive. If that line is crossed, it may not be a long step to removing the organs of normal dying persons while they are still alive. As Krauthammer says, “The heart, say, from a person not-quite-dead might be less deteriorated and thus more useful for transplantation.” The Council recognizes this fear, which it deals with under the label “Slippery Slope Concerns”: “[M]any fear that individuals who are in a persistent vegetative state, infants with profound neurological injury, and elderly adults with severe dementia would be considered acceptable sources of organs.” To reassure us that this particular slope is not all that slippery, the Council offers analogies: “When patients requested permission to reject life-sustaining treatment, opponents argued that granting such permission would open the way to euthanasia.” That remark is not terribly comforting, since a society grown accustomed to the removal of life-sustaining treatment is now moving towards assisted suicide, and very probably from there to euthanasia. It will certainly occur to someone that a person seeking assisted suicide or euthanasia could be rendered unconscious and his or her organs “harvested” while the person is alive. The persons wish would be carried out and the organs would be in better condition than if death had occurred before the organ removal. Doctors will make the same case the AMA’s Council makes for removing the organs of living anencephalics: there are “important, unmet social needs” and the donor is not really harmed. And a further step is likely to be taken: patients who have not requested euthanasia will be subjected to it nonetheless. There is, after all, a very great unmet social need for organs. This may be dismissed as wholly unrealistic fear-mongering. I do not think it should be.

A
SSISTED
S
UICIDE AND
E
UTHANASIA

Decisions about life and death in one area influence such decisions in others. Despite assurances that the abortion decisions did not start us down a slippery and very steep slope, that is clearly where we are, and gathering speed. The movement to make assisting suicides legal was made virtually inevitable by the Supreme Court’s
creation of a right to abortion. The power of the abortion right to influence opinion about assisted suicide, and soon, euthanasia, arises from the fact that by now we have all come to realize, despite the philosophical fog the pro-abortionists throw up, that abortions destroy human lives for the convenience of others. So long as we permitted ourselves to think that the embryo or the fetus was an undifferentiated piece of tissue, abortion had no implications for other takings of life. But now we know better. The result is that a moral line has been crossed and we are on our way to assisted suicide and euthanasia. Modern liberalism’s obsession with the autonomy of the individual is taking us to a culture of death. Ironically, the freedom of the individual to choose death has made it far easier for others to choose his death. The autonomy is often theirs, not his.

The attack on the statutes banning assisted suicide derives its emotional power from the picture painted by the partisans of the right-to-die movement: a terminally ill patient with nothing but intense suffering between him and death. The picture is, in large measure, false. There are ways of managing pain in most of the terminally ill. Something other than pure compassion must be in play. There are, moreover, many people who are in constant discomfort, physical or emotional, but who are not terminally ill. Why should they be denied the relief of assisted suicide? There are 31,000 suicides annually in the United States, and only 2 to 4 percent of those are by people who are terminally ill.
19
Many people have an urgent desire to be released from life. Dr. Jack Kevorkian, whose macabre trade of helping people out of this world elicits considerable public approval, does not confine his “practice” to the terminally ill, and a large percentage of his “patients” are not in that condition. It is telling, however, that he presents himself as one who aids the suffering and dying.

It is, in any event, curious that there should be a demand by those not helpless for assistance in committing suicide. The thing is not all that difficult. There is an abundant supply of high buildings and bridges. If the candidate lives where there are none, or shrinks from the pain of an abrupt landing, there is the gas oven in the kitchen, carbon monoxide from the automobile in the garage, an overdose of sleeping pills, and a variety of other painless ways of shuffling off. For many would-be suicides, however, these are
apparently not sufficient. They would be if all that were involved was the individual’s assertion of his or her personal autonomy. “Yet,” as Elizabeth Kristol writes, “the ‘right to choose’ is precisely what assisted suicide is not about. The unique service offered by professional suicide assistants is actually an escape from the burden of autonomous choice…. [T]he ultimate responsibility for taking one’s life … can be validated by a doctor, an expert we have come to entrust with a wide range of decisions regarding our well-being.“
20

Kristol perhaps understates the role physicians will sometimes play. They may well initiate and urge the idea of suicide or euthanasia. As Judge John Noonan observed in a Ninth Circuit panel opinion subsequently overturned by the
en banc court:
“Physician neutrality and patient autonomy, independent of their physician’s advice, are largely myths. Most patients do what their doctors recommend. As an eminent commission concluded, ‘Once the physician suggests suicide or euthanasia, some patients will feel that they have few, if any, alternatives but to accept the recommendation.”’
21

This reality puts assisted suicide in a somewhat more sinister light, as it does euthanasia. Euthanasia, in which the doctor does the actual killing, is only a half step beyond assisted suicide. It is sure to arrive as accepted practice if assisted suicide is accepted. The courts that have found assisted suicide to be a right have not specified the safeguards that must be followed. We can see the difficulties that will attend any effort to provide safeguards by looking at the conditions required by Oregon’s Death With Dignity Act, adopted in 1994. The patient must, for example, make three requests for assistance with suicide (the third one witnessed, transcribed, and signed), and two physicians must determine that the patient has six months or less to live. A physician may then prescribe a lethal dose of medication.

Other books

The Clandestine Circle by Mary H.Herbert
Special Ops Exclusive by Elle Kennedy
The Mystery of the Cupboard by Lynne Reid Banks
The Ogre of Oglefort by Eva Ibbotson
The Story Keeper by Lisa Wingate
Material Girl by Ervin, Keisha